 |
Arlyne Moi
Towards a Justifiable Conception of ‘the Autonomous Artwork’
in Today’s Artworld
|
Thesis for a "Hovedfag" in Philosophy at
the University of Bergen - Spring 2005.
Back to table of contents
- Next chapter
CHAPTER 2. BACKGROUND AND ROOTS OF THE EXPRESSION
‘AUTONOMOUS ARTWORK’
Auto, self, and nomos, law: Autonomos occurs in
ancient Greek prose and poetry, meaning living under one’s own laws.[25] From this it is easy
to understand why ‘autonomy’ in every-day English is synonymous with
independent, self-governing, free or not being controlled
by external forces. These notions are preserved in Kantian moral
philosophy, which contrasts ‘autonomous’ with ‘heteronymous’ as follows:
Heteronymous actions are determined by conditions, goals and values,
while autonomous actions follow the inner law (the categorical imperative),
which determines our status as rational beings, and therefore is the
foundation for human freedom (the hallmark of humanity). I, by contrast,
imagine the word “autonomous” as a homunculus with bulbous protrusions
stretching out in numerous directions; never reposed, restlessly it
moves about, stretching one arm towards one concept, another arm towards
another, and a third limb out towards something else. Perhaps it has
no essential aspects and is just a malleable shell, but near to its
heart remains some fairly stable cognates, pinned by constant use.
Nomos
The Perseus website[26]
presents nomos as that which is in habitual practice.
Its first interpretation leans towards usage, custom, what is
the custom in a certain city-state. Custom implies that things
are according to it; the nomos is something already established and
other things either follow or are contrary to it. Things may be done
for no other apparent reason than to follow the custom. In that case,
the act is done for sake of tradition and to fulfil a formal
requirement. For tradition, there is a focus upon fulfilling
an entrenched schema, as reflected in: “But we have to go to mass
because we always go to mass.” As formal requirement, we bend the knee,
even without a contrite heart. From the homunculus analogy, at the centre
of nomos is custom, and close at hand is law, ordinance, statute,
and decrees. Authority. But the malleable nomos bears negation
in its luggage: a-nomos, anomaly, no law, no habitual practice.
For the artiszan, ignorance of the rules of art, failure to conform
to them, unsystematic, inaccurate, unskilful: as such, the artisan
would be without art, uncreative and has no trade or
profession. The Greeks found this term particularly useful
when judging artisans; it would have been impossible to imagine artists
creating without rules. But more than this, without nomos, the
art or artisan could not even be recognized.
In ancient Greek literature, nomos personified is Orpheus. This
stretches the arms of nomos out to enfold melody or strain,
for nomos was used to refer to early melodies created for the lyre,
as an accompaniment to epic texts. The terms harmonikos, harmozô
are close by: tuning instruments, a thing in harmony with itself
or other objects. Adapting instruments—or, for that matter, adapting
anything to anything else entails harmony; the shoe must harmonize with
the user. So adaptation rubs against nomos: Things have to be
able to fit on or to or be according to, to be
adaptable. The thing suits another figure. Suiting or accommodation
now are formally joined with betrothal, making a troth between,
setting in order one’s marital situation; a regulated relation. It seems
to indicate that the Greek term archô (rule, ruled) is near to
the heart of nomos. The husband rules, the wife accommodates,
and the person with the soul of a slave is naturally suited for taking
orders. Moreover, the tool used by carpenters—the ruler—is an embodiment
of nomos. So also is the despot, for as soon as nomos
is set in place, the self has only two choices: It is either in violation
of, or is in subjection to nomos, for it is, in this traditional
understanding, the other of the self.
Auto: The self
The self is a question never resolved, and I will not attempt
to resolve it here, but it seems useful to think of the self is a subject
constituted through choices and actions that have become the object
of reflective activity. Traditionally construed as a consciousness of
being in the world, of being differentiated from the rest of nature
and God, while yet in a relationship with them, a self was thought important
to ground experience and action in, inasmuch as it functions as the
witness of experience, or the witness of reflection grounded in or constituting
consciousness. As such, the self’s ability to reflect over itself shows
it is already involved in a dialectic of normativity, hence it would
be a relation of actions grounded in material processes. Plato made
the self/soul out to be the seer or knower of Truth, Beauty and Goodness
(Phaedrus 246; 248d), and he readily admitted that it is impossible
to say what the self/soul is, so all we can do is to say what it is
like.[27]
Like Plato, Kant noted that the self cannot be experienced
empirically, but it can be thought or assumed and justified through
the indirect evidence of the empirical self.
‘Autonomous’ combined with the artwork-self
When the adjective under scrutiny joins with ‘artwork’, auto
or self refers to the artwork. This is trivial, but significant
because, when autonomy is predicated of the artwork, it immediately
acquires honorary personhood. Yet in the same manoeuvre, ‘autonomous
artwork’ is revealed as mysterious because what applies to the self
of a person would also have to apply to an artwork. But how can a thing
we intuitively assume is not endowed with life or spirit, lacking consciousness
or self-volition, become more than a material object? It would
have to have a soul or at least something non-tangible about it. The
artwork thus becomes a fetish-object in the sense of ‘an object possessed
by a spirit’. When the notion of self refers to the artwork,
the empirical artwork becomes indirect evidence for the work’s transcendental
self.[28]
The mysterious, non-tangible self of the artwork—its honorary personhood
and self-consciousness—can perhaps be more understandable (even if still
objectionable) if we recall that, when ‘autonomous’ and ‘artwork’ were
first lumped together in the nineteenth-century, this was the Romantic
era, which generally rejected neo-classical ideals of rationality; the
goal was to cultivate non-rational aspects of human thought. It is also
worth noting that by attributing personhood to artworks, this may actually
be a device for denoting something in the receiver’s mental activity,
which when verbalized, is transposed onto objects and reified.
Meanwhile, the consequences of predicating autonomy for the artwork
is that what was formerly understood as other than the artwork—general
rules found in symbols systems or in other selves—now becomes internalized.
The artwork-self sets up its own nomos, its own other,
to which it internally subjects itself. So autonomy does not
imply no law, anarchy or ‘anything-goes’; rather, the laws simply are
not given from outside.
Since the artwork is a historical, timely event, its “self” has opportunities
for change and re-creation contingent upon what it experiences, and
upon the synthesis of its thoughts and actions, as it were. It would
be a situation in which various activities occur, and where a
will can be expressed or suppressed. The work that is autonomous is
both sovereign and subject; bound by laws, but only those it
has itself made, derived through habitual, integral practices.
The antithesis of the autonomous artwork would be the heteronymous
artwork: Something produced through adherence to external laws,
and accomplishing external purposes. It would not be independent from
other institutions of society—e.g., traditional folk art, applied artworks
like advertising jingles, or contemporary popular art.
From this initial “dip” into ‘autonomous artwork’, let us look backwards,
to Kant, who is an important philosophical starting point for establishing
the various concepts of the work’s autonomy used in today’s artworld.
It is to Kant’s judgment of taste we now turn, to understand
the “building blocks” of these conceptions.
Endnotes
[25] Liddell and Scott Greek-English Lexicon for Internet.
[26] http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0057%3Aentry%3D%2371006
[27] Even materialistic theories
might agree, for although the self is a mix of biological material
processes, when we examine the materials of our bodies, do they reveal
all the workings of the self? Although the self might not exist without
material activity, it is perhaps still not the same as material
processes.
[28] See chapter 4, “Aesthetic
Realism”, pp. 37-41.
|