 |
Arlyne Moi
Towards a Justifiable Conception of ‘the Autonomous Artwork’
in Today’s Artworld
|
Thesis for a "Hovedfag" in Philosophy at
the University of Bergen - Spring 2005.
Back to table of contents
- Next chapter
CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
Since the nineteenth-century, the autonomous artwork[1] has been one of the touchstones
in the field of art. It is often baked into discussions about artistic
creation, identity, interpretation, and value. When the expression is
not specifically mentioned, it is implicitly present in other usage
such as “the artist-genius”, “the work in itself”, “originality”, “the
hermetic work”, “non-purposiveness”, “ineffectuality”, “art’s separation
from epistemology and morality”, “the artworld’s play-logic”, ‘transgressive
art’, and ‘Modern art’, etc. If interlocutors do not assume some version
of the work’s autonomy, they are often reacting against it, challenging
it.
‘The autonomous artwork’ is a controversial issue
Interpretations of Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgment[2] §1-60 established ‘autonomy’
as pre-eminently relevant for thinking about ‘a field of art’, and throughout
the nineteenth and twentieth-centuries of Modernism, its relation to
the field—artworld[3]—complexified, culminating in a
swamp of disparate conceptions, all vying for legitimacy. Under High
Modernism, with the exception of directions such as Social Realism (e.g.,
Diego Rivera), most Western artists were pretty much on the political
periphery;[4]
as long as their expressions were confined to the art institutional
setting, they received little political interference, at least on the
face of things.[5]
Yet today’s artworld experiences a transition: Now artists are leaving
art-institutional settings and entering the everyday spaces where historical
consequences, instrumentality, responsibility, personal ethics, relations
of power and stated intentions are readily apparent. One pertinent Norwegian
example of this transition is Kunst Passasjen located in the
Oslo Metro, a typically commercial space [Illustration
1][6]
Other examples are Bergen Kunstforening, Nasjonalmuseet in Oslo
and the Astrup Fearnley Museum of Modern Art, Oslo. Bergen
Kunstforening was, until a few years ago, the venue for artworks traditionally
understood as autonomous; it has now been displaced with Kunsthallen,
which mounts demonstratively politically enmeshed exhibitions.[7] Nasjonalmuseet in Oslo recently re-hung their
“basis exhibition” according to themes, some of which are markedly morally
enmeshed (‘the vulnerable human being’). As for Astrup Fearnely
Museum, they regularly mount exhibitions highlighting artworks relating
to our common everyday life-world; expressions urgently engage with
content such as temporality, memory, commercialism, consumerism and
social commentary.[8] These four examples are instances
of late modern ideology[9] attempting to dismantle the
distinctions famously put in place by Kant, between the domains of aesthetics,
epistemology and morality. Still, in spite of the dissolution of clear
institutional boundaries and demonstrative instrumentality, many of
the dogmas and dreams about the autonomous artwork continue—some
of the basic assumptions of Kantian[10] (i.e. Modern) aesthetic theory
are kept, Kant’s “Copernican turn” in aesthetics[11]—but
these assumptions are ever more critically crowded by questions concerning
the social-political function of art, artist’s moral responsibilities,
the psychology of aesthetic perception, the sociological relations of
art, gender or race-related issues, and the role of art in interpreting
the needs and desires of the polis.[12]
Furthermore, if one accepts, as I do, that ready-mades are art, one
must accept that anything can be art.[13] Because of this, the late modern ideological trends that deny
moral/epistemological independence of artworks seem to make good sense,
because the Kantian aesthetic point of view—the view that swept
moral and epistemological considerations aside—becomes increasingly
difficult to maintain simultaneously as receivers experience it as incomprehensible
and irrelevant. For example, formerly it was common to address AIDS
in news media, law-courts, health-industry publications and from the
pulpit, but now this theme is directly addressed in art. By changing
the context in which AIDS is broached, a morass of moral concerns arise:
Intuitively, it seems misguided to don a so-called disinterested attitude
and restrict one’s reception to “art-internal” concerns such as the
golden mean, or to focus on taste, or the work’s supposed indeterminate
purposiveness. Can we assign AIDS-related artworks a separate sphere
of value on account of some understanding of their autonomy? What makes
them different from AIDS-related non-art? Andrew Bowie, for example,
asserts that the significance of an artwork lies in its ability to reveal,
by some special status, what nothing else can.[14] But hasn’t the loss of an exclusive institutional setting, political
and instrumental artworks, and the ready-made, made a mockery of that
claimed special status? ‘The autonomous artwork’, in its many guises,
is under redoubled attack. At one end of the spectrum of today’s artworld,
advocate of Modernism could say:
‘The autonomous artwork’ remains an important expression for the artworld;
it denotes something beyond the threshold of determinate knowledge,
if not moral constraints, and it is not directly instrumental. ‘The
autonomous artwork’ is crucial for ensuring the artist’s freedom of
expression and art’s contribution within advanced capitalist societies.
Moreover, there are many justifiable ways of interpreting ‘autonomous
artwork’, which share in traditional Kantian commitments.
At the other end of the spectrum, a dissenter could respond:
‘The autonomous artwork’, in most of its interpretations, is
wishful thinking. It hides a multitude of deceit. If anything about
the artwork were considered autonomous today, it would be to the detriment
of cultural life generally. Artworks are directly instrumental and inter-relational
with epistemological and moral concerns. Most aspects of the Kantian
moments of aesthetic judgment are defunct.
One international example of these competing voices is Lucy Lippard
and Hilton Kramer: When Lippard, in a catalogue text for the Art
& Ideology exhibit (1990) at the New Museum of Contemporary
Art in New York, stated: “All art is ideological and all art is
used politically by the right or the left.” Kramer replied: “[…] this
movement toward the politicization of art in this country is an attempt
to turn back the cultural political clock to the Stalinist social consciousness
of the 1930’s.[15] Yet these competing voices are
also heard in Norway: In 2003, fifty-nine Norwegian artists and art-professionals
were surveyed on the theme of autonomy.[16]
To the question: “If art is autonomous, then what is it dependent
on?” one participant answered “The magic of the night”.
Another replied “Itself”, while a third answered “A whole lot of people,
who are willing to make use of its physical potential”. To the question
“Why is art morally responsible?” answers varied: “Because art has to
do with qualities, language, distinctions that involve communication
between human beings.” Contrariwise, “Art in itself has no moral responsibility”.
The participants were also asked about the work in relation to the artist,
with the question: “Why is an artist not morally responsible?” Answers
ranged from: “Because he is an artist” and “A morally responsible artist
is no artist,” to “I don’t think it is possible to both call yourself
an artist, or even a human being for that matter, and at the same time
claim that this is not morally demanding.” Hence, both internationally
and locally, ‘the autonomous artwork’ is a controversial issue, ambulating
from being something wanted and claimed, to being something contested
or denied.
‘The autonomous artwork’ is a confused issue
There are a myriad of construals of ‘the autonomous artwork’ jumbled
in the cacophony of the artworld: the artist’s private expression;
ontological independence; the separate status of the artwork in society,
its separation from truth and moral judgments; the receiver’s disinterested
reception; the work’s radical ambiguity; its self-sufficiency for either
interpretation or justification; under-determination by language; transcendental
essence, transgression of norms, non-purposiveness; an empty game; powerlessness
or infectivity; the fragment; absolutely un-reducible unit; non-defineability;
just to mention a few. One problem, as I see it, of what has been
written on the theme of ‘the autonomous artwork’, is that writers tends
towards “myopia”; there is a lack an appreciation of the enormity of
different concurrent conceptions.[17]
Indicative of this “myopia” is Atle Kittang’s very useful essay, “Til
forsvar for autonomiestetikken—rett forstått”, where he only acknowledges
one explication of ‘autonomous artwork’ as legitimate.[18] Meanwhile, many art-professional’s
practice seems to indicate that they have not reflected much over what
they want ‘autonomous artwork’ to mean, and how the different conceptions
can conflict, and how ‘the autonomous work’ may be distinct from instrumental
works. Self-contradictions arise. For example, when Dror Feiler’s
Snow White and the Madness of Truth (2004) [Illustration 2] made international news,
the art critic Yoram Kaniuk,[19] in his discussion of Feiler’s work, did not
seem to be expressing an Adornoesque duplicity when he said: “Kunsten
er ikke hellig. Kunsten forandrer ikke verden.” (Art is not
holy. Art cannot change [anything in] the world.) According to a reasonable
interpretation, Kaniuk’s assertion is problematic: The first sentence
indicates that the artwork is not autonomous because it is not cut off
from human moral and epistemological judgments. Therefore, we presume,
it can be judged according to some standard of truth and morality. But
the second sentence contradicts this: Art is ineffectual with regard
to the daily activities of humans. Thus it is “holy” in the sense of
blameless; we must assume the work is not able to encourage people to
hate or kill, empathize or mourn; it is merely a goal unto itself, has
no determinate significance for events in the world. Thus from the same
mouth, the artwork is first criticized for wielding power (the instrumentalist
position) and thereafter criticized for lacking power (an autonomist
position). Another inconsistency about the Feiler incident was that
Israel’s ambassador Zvi Mazel, a significant political person, was invited
to an instrumental artworld but thereafter scolded for not conforming
to an autonomous artworld’s rules. Yet it may be argued that
Mazel himself defended his “demounting performance” by playing the role
of autonomous “the artist-genius”, claiming to act from feelings without
cognitive deliberation: “I acted out of how I felt, I could not do things
any other way.”[20]
But are these just instances of inconsistency, or could the artwork’s
autonomy and its instrumentality—the touted double character—coherently
co-exist? Here is, as I see it, the contemporary scenario: The artist
ardently desires that her works be instrumental (useful, significant
and valuable in the political, morally laden every-day world); simultaneously
she claims the work’s autonomy (it is free to address any theme
via any media and be presented in any venue).[21] As soon as the consequences of the work’s instrumentality come
to bear, the artist runs for cover under various and sundry of Modernism’s
conceptions of autonomy. Then the whole language game of ‘the
autonomous artwork’ is deployed.[22]
This scenario poses a striking problem because most theories designed
to account for the work’s autonomy rely for their paradigmatic examples
upon Modern artworks, preferably from the first half of the twentieth-century—Formalist
and Abstract Expressionist works, poetry and literature by the likes
of Joyce and Mallarmé. These examples are invoked to justify the freedoms
of late modern, demonstratively instrumental, political, and morally
enmeshed works.[23] Insofar as contemporary artworks are defended
from onslaughts by way of theories, arguments and examples from Modernism’s
hay day, ‘the autonomous artwork’ may denote a closed epoch; it was
an important concept, but perhaps it is mostly irrelevant for contemporary
works? In any case, if it is going to be dismissed, or if it is still
a viable notion for today, the tangle of conceptions needs to be thought
through carefully once again, and, as well as reflecting over how the
various understandings intertwine, their claims and arguments should
be tested in light of today’s art.
Problemstilling and thesis statement
Can the disparate understandings of ‘the autonomous artwork’ be laid
out, discussed, reflected over, and a revitalized synthesis be constructed,
which could be relevant for contemporary artworks?[24] My thesis-statement is that in light of
post-Duchampian and demonstratively political-instrumental artworks,
the field of possibilities has narrowed for what ‘autonomous artwork’
should mean. With a narrowed meaning, the expression ‘autonomous artwork’
can regain relevance for today’s artworld. The narrowed meaning
I suggest retains some sceptical insights as expressed by Kant himself,
but also some insights from his many interpreters. Furthermore, the
notion of ‘an undecidable character’ can help overcome some of the problems
experienced with ‘the double character’ of artworks.
Overview of chapters
Chapter 2 begins by looking backwards, at the roots of the expression
‘autonomous artwork’. It also brings to light some of the assumptions
inadvertently swallowed when the adjective ‘autonomous’ is joined with
‘artwork’. The backwards glance resumes in chapter 3, with what ‘autonomous
artwork’ meant in light of Kant’s judgment of taste, which provided
a veritable deluge of “building blocks” for establishing a whole field
of autonomy for art. Chapter 4 follows up with an alternating account
and discussion of the most prominent understandings of ‘autonomous artwork’
prevalent today. These understandings tend to selectively appropriate
and build upon aspects of the Kantian synthesis of what ‘autonomous
artwork’ entailed. Admittedly, the task of chapter 4 is overly ambitious;
some of the discussions are sparse, yet I see no way around it if one
is to overcome the myopic problem addressed on page 4. In order
to comply with the limitations of 115 pages, I strategically choose
to treat in a more cursory fashion the discussion of the artwork’s autonomy
as being situated within the art institution; and choose instead to
focus on the Kantian legacy, which entails that the work be viewed in
light of the artist and the receiver, and the ontological approaches
with both weak and strong commitments. The art institution will nevertheless
be ubiquitous throughout this paper. The chapter concludes by constructing
a provisional synthesis of the moments of autonomy for contemporary
artworks. Meanwhile, some of these moments are still problematic. Chapter
5 examines and discusses some of the views of Heidegger, Blanchot and
Derrida. The goal is not to exhaustively present and discuss the aesthetic
philosophies of these three thinkers—115 pages do not provide the scope
for that—but to examine how they understand the artwork as autonomous.
This can shed more light on the problem-points of chapter 4: the assertion
that material and formal features are primary and thus grounds for
asserting the work’s autonomy; the assertion that the artwork’s
autonomy is based on the fundamental incommensurability between the
artwork’s symbolic form and the symbolic forms of speech and language;
and the notion of the artwork’s double character. As the chapter
wanes, a second tentative list of moments of autonomy is suggested,
which is a synthesis of thoughts from these three thinkers. Where they
disagree, Derrida’s undecidability thesis is given preference. Chapter
6 takes the two synthesis of moments from chapters 4 and 5, compares
and discusses, and then hazards a third hybrid of moments of autonomy
for the contemporary artwork. It is, I feel, a sober, careful and justifiable
list that does not make large claims about the work’s autonomy, but
what remains is highly significant. Chapter 6 concludes with the following
question: Is the project—of constructing a conception of ‘autonomous
artwork’ that would be justifiable for contemporary artworks—obsolete?
I conclude in chapter 7 with a review of the main points.
Throughout the paper, I have tried to address the problem expressed
by Friedrich von Schlegel, that in the so-called philosophy of art,
one of two things is usually missing: either the philosophy or the art.
Prompted by Schlegel, I have, where possible, integrated the matters
under discussion with talk of specific artworks, many of which are in
the Astrup Fearnley Collection, Oslo. My hope is that the works will
not be reduced to “mere illustrations”, but that they can be occasions
for thinking through the problems of ‘the autonomous artwork’.
Endnotes
[1] Throughout this paper I use
Arthur Danto’s coinage “artwork”, with “work” as synonym.
[2] Kant’s Critique of Judgment will here to
fore be referred to as CJ.
[3] By “artworld”, what I mean
is a microcosm generally understood as the social, economic and political
domain in which artists both work and find support. It is a domain
made up of many people who cooperate by means of shared conventions
that allow them to coordinate their activities. Through repeated cooperation
by people who are similar enough in their function to be considered
the same, we can speak of an artworld. (See, for example, Becker,
1998, p. 148.) According to some thinkers, it is qualitatively different
than the rest of culture; according to others, it reflects the general
culture and is overwhelmingly connected to it. Some thinkers would
make a distinction between artists on the one hand, and the rest of
the artworld on the other. In this paper, “the artworld”, “the art
institution(s)” “the field of art” are treated as synonyms. Within
the artworld there are many institutions (e.g., museums, art publishers,
but there are also habitual practices which are institutionalized).
[4] By “political” I mean broadly
“life in the polis”: political, religious and other everyday concerns.
[5] I allude to the CIA’s involvement
in Modern Art during the Cold War, as addressed by Frances Stonor
Saunders engaging book Who Paid the Piper? London: Granta Books,
1999. Saunders tells how the CIA heavily supported non-figurative
visual art, abstract music, Modern Art theory and cultural activities
that could fulfil Cold War propaganda purposes. Her chapter 16, “Yanqui
Doodles” deals with the CIA’s involvement in MoMA.
[6] It starts near the passageway between the lobbies
at Jernbanetorget Metro Station.
[7] Spring 2005, the Bergen Kunsthall
mounted Time Suspended, which deals with the theme refugees
and human rights: the challenge of longstanding conflicts. This
exhibition is a collaborative effort on behalf of video-artists and
human rights organizations such as the Raftos Foundation. As well
as viewing videos dealing with the Israel/Palestine conflict, the
Kunsthall has “curated” a seminar series by non-art professionals
(politicians, journalists, judges, human rights activists and researchers)
to present their views to gallery-goers.
[8] A good example is Everyday
Aesthetics, Astrup Fearnley Museum of Modern Art, Oslo, 27.09.03-30.11.03.
Among the artists represented: Louise Lawler, Sherrie Levine, Richard
Prince, Jeff Koons and Charles Ray. For anyone familiar with contemporary
art, these names will indicate Postmodern approaches.
[9] I use the term “late modern”
rather than “Postmodern”. By this, I refer to ideologues who might
be considered Postmodern, in the sense that they want to deconstruct
the distinction between the domains of art, morality and epistemology:
Jacques Derrida and Roland Barthes, but also American authors writing
in the October Book series, MIT Press, such as Douglas Crimp, Hal
Foster and Rosalind Krauss.
[10] By ‘Kantian’, what is
referred to is the many interpretations of Kant’s Critique of Judgment,
be they focused on the psychological aspects of aesthetic experience
or the formal and expressive dimensions of aesthetic experience.
[11] What I mean by “Copernican
turn” is the insight that it is not what the artwork holds for
a individual to discover, but what the individual brings to the work,
both a priori features and attitude that constitute and determine
their aesthetic experience. (See chapter 2).
[12] A good example is the
“ Cultural Studies” movement, where the traditional study of Art History
is augmented or displaced with Visual Cultural Studies, more akin
to social science. Contrast, for example, Jonathan Harris’ The
New Art History: A Critical Introduction (London: Routledge, 2001),
with Ernst Gombrich’s classic The Story of Art: Gombrich’s
chapters follow chronological history, while Harris’ book is organized
according to themes dealing with capitalist modernity, feminism, the
subject’s identity, sexuality, structures and meaning in art and society.
[13] Here I am stating an
important assumption. When Duchamp’s ready-mades attained the status
of art, a revolution in the artworld occurred: Either the artworld
entered a new dispensation (something that before could not have been
art now could be art), or something was realized about art that never
before had been apparent, namely, that calling something art
is the primary aesthetic judgment. And ‘art’ is increasingly understood
as being, in some respects, a proper name like “George” (this
will be discussed in chapter 4). Meanwhile, in asserting that anything
can be art, I am also already assuming an important sort of autonomy
for the artwork, and will throughout this paper—that in being able
to be anything, the work is independent from the necessity of being
something, as was traditionally understood as a criteria for art,
prior to the advent of non-figuration. Accepting ready-mades as artworks
entails already having accepted a modicum of autonomy for the artwork.
[14] Bowie, 1995, p. 34.
[15]http://www.uic.edu/classes/ad/ad382/sites/AEA/AEA_05/AEA_05a.html
[16] Frigstad, 2003, pp.37-62.
[17] An important exception is Peter Bürger’s excellent
“Critique of Autonomy” in Kelly, vol. 1, 1994, pp. 175-178, where
he mentions at least 8 different construals. Still, there are many
he does not mention. This problem reveals Kant’s wisdom in describing
the autonomous field as having many moments. (See chapter 3).
[18] Translation: “In Defence of the Aesthetics of
Autonomy—Correctly Understood”. As far as I can see, what I call the
myopic problem is perhaps a necessary evil, and perfectly understandable
in relational to the Modern research-university scholars’ in-depth
focus on one small segment of a field, which begets the highly specialized
‘fag idiot’ or ‘nerd’ as we would say in English. I am not trying
to knock Kittang, as I feel that his New Critical approach is one
of the most valuable understandings of the work’s autonomy; it is
just too limited.
[19] http://www.artdaily.com/links.asp?idl=28&id=322;
Nyberg, Jan, “Den uskjønne kunsten”, Bergens Tidende 23 January,
2004; Rosenbergs, Göran, ”Ambassadøren og antisemittismen”, Bergens
Tidende, 24 January, 2004.
[20] Ibid.
[21] An excellent example was in 2003, when art-students,
under the banner of “kunstens viktig funksjon: å skape offentlig
debatt” (art’s important function: to create public debate), broke
into a private house (in disrepair) and started altering it. They
admitted breaking the law, but “art’s important function” was above
the law (in this case, the function was to point out the inconsistency
that, while it is unlawful to let one’s car rot on the roadside, it
is lawful let your house fall into disrepair). (“Protesterer med kunst”,
in Bergens Tidende, 22 October, 2003, p. 2.)
[22] ‘Language game’, in this
context, means all the things expressed in phrases such as purposiveness
without purpose, taste, the powerlessness or ineffectuality
of art, the incommensurability of aesthetic phenomena to concepts,
or the autonomy of reception, etc., the web of Modern notions
used to defend and justify the artwork.
[23] Examples are legion,
but three famous examples suffice: Robert Maplethorpe’s X Portfolio
was defended against obscenity charges by reference to his use of
the “golden mean” and formal compositional features, the autonomy
of the institutional setting, “disinterested interest”. (See Crimp,
1993, pp. 6-13) To this Arthur Danto exclaimed, “[These museum directors]
are arrogant Kantians who treated these extraordinary images as formal
exercises…” Arthur C. Danto, "Censorship and Subsidy in the Arts,"
Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences 47/1
(Oct. 1993), pp. 25–61. http://projects.gsd.harvard.edu/appendx/dev/issue2/jarzombek/index1.htm
André Serrano’s Piss Christ defended by Lucy
Lippard according to the dictates of “art-internal” criteria. http://mentalhelp.net/books/books.php?type=de&id=1124:
“The work is a large colour print, 60 x 40 inches. It is a Cibachrome
print. This means it is glossy with deeply saturated colours, and
its surface is very delicate, easily ruined by a fingerprint or a
slight speck of dust. The image is not recognizable as a crucifix
floating in the artist's own urine. The jar cannot be read from the
print. Rather, a crucifix is presented in a golden, rosy medium within
which constellations of tiny bubbles have been frozen in space. For
all we know the crucifix could be suspended in amber or polyurethane.
The formal qualities of the work are, in fact, quite mysterious and
beautiful.” Lippard also used arguments based upon the title’s ambiguity,
the artist’s private expression, the artist’s stated intentions and
the context of the autonomous art institution. http://www.csulb.edu/~jvancamp/361_r7.html
is a congressional transcript record.
When Sally Mann’s Immediate Family was accused
of paedophilic content, they were defended with the claim that all
the receiver is doing is looking in a mirror of her own values. http://www.sallymann.org/index-1.html
(See ch. 4).
[24] By ‘contemporary artworks’, I choose to limit
my focus to works such as are found in the Astrup Fearnley Museum
of Modern Art, Oslo.
|